The Difficult Necessity of Empathy

With whom do you empathize the most? And how hard do you try to empathize with others?

Empathy in a carton
(Have you taken your dose of empathy today? “Empathy in a carton,” by Geoff Jones, on Flickr under Creative Commons.)

I thought about empathy as I was watching the video of the NYPD takedown of Eric Garner. Mr. Garner was approached by and ultimately tackled by several policemen, which unfortunately resulted in his death.

As I watched, I tried to put myself in each person’s position to try to determine, if I had been them, what I might have been thinking and feeling at the time and whether I would have been able to act any differently. If I had been the first officer, would I have felt threatened when Mr. Garner started waving his arms around? If I had been the officer who approached Mr. Garner from behind, or any of the other officers, would I have felt that I had to resort to dangerous tactics due to his size advantage?

And, at the heart of the matter: if I had been Mr. Garner, would I have felt threatened by the officers present? Would I have thought it somewhat ridiculous that I was being harassed when the only danger I posed was that a few more people would risk slow death from cancer and some fewer dollars would make it into the city coffers, when those officers could be chasing violent felons who posed much greater threats to society? When I turned away from the first officer, would I have been thinking that my best course of action was to try to escape? When so many of them piled on me, would I have struggled to break free simply out of fear for my life?

I went through a similar exercise while reading the grand jury proceedings and looking at the crime scene photographs from Ferguson, regarding the Michael Brown case. Again, I tried to put myself in each person’s position.

If I had been __, would I have felt threatened? Would I have felt afraid? Would I have found it irritating or even maddening to be looked at, spoken to, or approached the way the other person did? Would I have felt within my rights to respond aggressively? Would I have had the self-control to stop before things went too far?

If you haven’t done so, try that exercise yourself. First put one party in the blank, and then the other. Do you come up with the same, or different, answers each time? And, more to the point of this post: do you find it easier to empathize with one party than with the other?

I think it’s human nature for us to find it easier to empathize with people with whom we share common bonds or common characteristics. Someone you know is easier to identify with than a stranger, and someone who is like you in some way is easier to identify with than someone who is very different from you.

But sometimes what is easy is not worthwhile, and what is difficult is most beneficial. Human nature aside, it seems important to go through the effort of trying to empathize to at least some degree with each party whenever we encounter a controversy or a tragedy — at the very least, it seems necessary to developing a fuller understanding of the issue, if not of the world. Failing to do so is not a vice, because it can be quite daunting, but refusing to make the attempt is no virtue.

Facebooktwitterpinterestlinkedinmailby feather

Considering an Unanswered Question about the Ferguson Events

I have not commented on the Michael Brown/Officer Darren Wilson case here on the blog. I preferred to wait until the grand jury had completed its investigation, which it did last week.

Justice
(“Justice,” by Don Sutherland, on Flickr under Creative Commons.)

Not that anyone cares much what I think about it, but I have a question that I have not seen raised anywhere.

Even after the grand jury’s results were released, I have continued to see reference to video and still images that “allegedly” show Brown robbing a store, or to the store itself as one that Brown “allegedly robbed,” but: if Michael Brown didn’t rob the store — i.e., if the person in the video is not him — then who did? Using the word “allegedly” may conform to some journalistic style manual, but continuing to say Brown was only “alleged” to have robbed the store seems at best naive and at worst, calculated.

We might give the press the benefit of its own supposed doubt. But if Michael Brown was the “gentle giant” his supporters believe he was, why didn’t his supporters track down the person who actually robbed the store? Why didn’t the hordes of sympathetic reporters roaming the streets of Ferguson and the greater Saint Louis area find and bring forward the actual perpetrator?

If someone else robbed that store, that would seem to be an important part of solidifying the image of Brown as a truly innocent victim on that August day. Given the lengths to which the press has gone to portray Brown in the best possible light, e.g., by selecting particular pictures to display, they might have been motivated to produce such a person. (The police would be under no such motivation, since they would have every reason to believe that the facts support the chronology that begins with Brown robbing the store.) In addition to the press, Michael Brown’s family and friends might be motivated to find the perpetrator, if such a person exists, in order to clear their son and friend’s name. But in the nearly 4 months since his death, I have not seen a single report that someone else committed that crime.

Why is that?

In fact, Dorian Johnson, who was in the store and later present at the shooting, testified to the grand jury that Brown not only stole Cigarillos from the store but did indeed shove the clerk — as seen in the video — in the process of leaving (see Volume 4 of the Grand Jury Proceedings, pages 32-7). We might consider the possibility that Johnson lied about the robbery — his testimony about the manner of Brown’s death did not match other witnesses’ testimony or the forensic evidence, for instance — but it seems likely that no one has come forward to confess to the crime or to identify someone other than Brown because no such person exists.
___

A Brief Aside on the Issue of Johnson’s Believability:

Both sides in the search for justice must be a bit disappointed in Dorian Johnson’s testimony. Johnson testified that Brown was shot while trying to surrender, casting doubt on Officer Wilson’s version of events, but his characterization of Brown’s interaction with the store clerk cast doubt on the “gentle giant” mystique as well. Should any one part of his testimony be taken as more accurate than another?

According to a new National Academy of Sciences report,

many factors influence the visual perceptual experience: dim illumination and brief viewing times, large viewing distances, duress, elevated emotions, and the presence of a visually distracting element such as a gun or a knife. Gaps in sensory input are filled by expectations that are based on prior experiences with the world. Prior experiences are capable of biasing the visual perceptual experience and reinforcing an individual’s conception of what was seen. We also have learned that these qualified perceptual experiences are stored by a system of memory that is highly malleable and continuously evolving, neither retaining nor divulging content in an informational vacuum. The fidelity of our memories to actual events may be compromised by many factors at all stages of processing, from encoding to storage to retrieval. Unknown to the individual, memories are forgotten, reconstructed, updated, and distorted. Therefore, caution must be exercised when utilizing eyewitness procedures and when relying on eyewitness identifications in a judicial context.

— Identifying the Culprit: Assessing Eyewitness Identification, by the Committee on Scientific Approaches to Understanding and Maximizing the Validity and Reliability of Eyewitness Identification in Law Enforcement and the Courts, National Research Council.

Certainly Johnson’s later observations involved larger distances than the encounter in the store as well as “duress, elevated emotions, and the presence of a visually distracting element such as a gun,” but that in itself would not be a reason to discount his testimony. This is where corroborating evidence comes into play, and unfortunately for Johnson (and for Brown’s supporters) the available evidence appears only to corroborate his version of events before he and Brown encountered Wilson.
___

Back to the main topic, this question — if Brown didn’t rob the store, who did? — brings up further, and more difficult, questions.

Can the press, and the family, and his most fervent supporters acknowledge that Michael Brown actually (rather than “allegedly”) robbed that store? If so, can they acknowledge the possibility that, flushed with the adrenaline and endorphin rush of a successful robbery that included a brief physical altercation, Brown might have either a) reacted out of fear of being arrested or b) considered himself capable of intimidating a police officer?

If Brown’s supporters persist in portraying him as completely innocent in this matter — indeed as some sort of paragon who was incapable of belligerence — then it is unlikely that they will ever be able to admit (or possibly even consider) that the other grand jury findings — that Brown was shot first while tussling with Wilson through the window of the police vehicle; ran away bleeding; turned around; and moved back toward Wilson — may be exactly as presented. I don’t know if that would be considered cognitive dissonance, or a refusal to think anything but the best about someone whose side they have taken.

But the “gentle giant” narrative seems to hinge on the lingering doubt among his supporters that Michael Brown actually robbed that store, in which case the unanswered question — if not him, then who? — seems to be apt, if not important.

Facebooktwitterpinterestlinkedinmailby feather

Refining My Position on Just About Everything: Don’t Punish Good Folks When Bad Things Happen

Often it seems to me that many of our laws — and quite a bit of the heated rhetoric I read and hear — derive from a tendency to try to correct or prevent bad things by punishing everyone, including those who aren’t responsible for the bad things. I’m against this.

Community Punishment Workshop
(“Community Punishment Workshop,” by amortize, on Flickr under Creative Commons.)

I first thought about this when I was writing my “If I Were My Own Representative” series, one of which was Part IV: My Touchstone for Voting:

My initial position would be to vote “no” on any bill that had a provision that would hurt some of our citizens, even if it helped some others. I would have to be convinced that the help was worth the hurt; i.e., that the hurt was along the lines as the necessary pain of surgery to correct a life-threatening condition.

If it wasn’t clear what effects some given legislation would have, whether it would hurt some people while helping some others, I would at least ASK. If no one could tell me, again my initial thought would be to vote against it.

I’m coming to believe this in more general terms than just politics: i.e., that in general we shouldn’t blame or punish good people when other people do bad things or allow them to happen. Let me lay out a few assumptions upon which I base this position:

  • There are some bad people in the world, who tend to do bad things. However,
  • Most people in the world are good or, if not actually good, at least not habitually bad.* Even so, some good people may occasionally do bad things (but, I think, usually by mistake or in extremis).
  • Bad things cannot be predicted with certainty, and sometimes not even with confidence.
  • When a person does a bad thing, and is considered likely to do more bad things, it is best to place that person in a position where it is more difficult for them to be able to do bad things.
  • When a person (good or bad) does a bad thing, and bad people may be inspired to follow their example, it is best to downplay the bad things rather than advertise or sensationalize them.
  • When a person (good or bad) does a bad thing, it is a mistake to assume that good people will follow the person’s example.
  • Because good people are the majority, and most good people are unlikely to follow the examples of people doing bad things, it is always a mistake to summarily limit the rights of good people (or strip rights from them) in response to bad things.
  • This approach will occasionally fail, because it is impossible to prevent all bad things or to identify all potentially bad people.

I don’t expect anyone particularly to agree with me on this (or anything else, for that matter), but that’s the way I’m approaching things right now.

___
*I offer this optional way of characterizing it for those for whom the doctrine of Original Sin, or Jesus’s “no one is good but God” statement (Matthew 19:17, Mark 10:18, Luke 18:19),prevents them from admitting that there may be good people in the world.

Facebooktwitterpinterestlinkedinmailby feather

When Does ‘I Want’ Become ‘You Must’?

I think it’s important that we remember that the Law of Supply and Demand does not state, “Someone else must supply what I demand.”

Economics Basics: Demand and Supply
(“Economics Basics: Demand and Supply,” by Fabio Venni, on Flickr under Creative Commons.)

We would do well to remember it when we “demand” anything, of anyone, whether we do so with a threat or simply without offering any recompense, and whether we do so to benefit ourselves or on behalf of others. It is one thing to make a request, or to suggest an exchange of value that someone else may consider, and quite another to make a demand.

The Rush song “Something for Nothing” comes to mind, e.g., “you can’t have freedom for free.”*

It seems to me like the most basic economics. We want (and even perhaps need) something that someone else has, and we either: request them to share it, offer to earn or purchase it, or demand to be given it. The first is mendicity, and meeting the request would be charity; the second is commerce and industry, and accepting the offer would lead to an exchange of value; the third may range from immaturity to larceny, and meeting the demand would seem to be little more than acquiescence and an invitation to further demands.

So far as I can tell, then, “I want” does not require or even imply “you must.”

___
*As much as I would like to quote more of the song, I’m not convinced a longer quote would be considered “fair use” and my respect for their copyright prevents me from doing so.

Facebooktwitterpinterestlinkedinmailby feather

Marriage Finally ‘Liberated’ From Matrimony?

It seems we need not bother calling marriage “matrimony” any more, since the institution no longer has much to do with motherhood.

0824: matrimony
(“0824: matrimony,” by EMILIE RHAUPP, on Flickr under Creative Commons.)

That used to be what the word meant, in one form dating as far back as the Romans. The English word “matrimony” came into use around 1300, and derives from the Old French word “matremoine” which in turn derives from the Latin word for marriage, matrimonium. That word itself combined matrem, meaning “mother,” with monium, meaning a state or condition of being. So the Latin word for wedlock meant, literally, the condition of motherhood.

Motherhood was, thus, an expected outcome of marriage.

For decades the US has gradually dissociated motherhood from marriage, honoring each less and less. Out-of-wedlock motherhood, once considered undesirable enough to be avoided by expedient marriages or other means, tragically including abortion, has become more acceptable — even while the actual work of motherhood has become far less respected. Single motherhood, it sometimes seems, is the only form of motherhood that is widely honored, perhaps because to be a successful single mother requires a heroic level of effort.

(Single motherhood is heroic, but that doesn’t make it preferable to being a mother who is part of a successful marriage. I imagine that many single mothers might prefer to have a partner with whom to share the costs and responsibilities of parenthood, just as many [if not most] people who are thought of as heroes might have preferred never to have been put in the situations which called for heroics in the first place.)

As the link between marriage and motherhood has disintegrated, marriage itself has lost its allure for many people. Adultery and divorce, which like single motherhood used to carry some stigma, seem to have almost become mainstream.

And with “marriages” between homosexuals becoming accepted practice — witness the US Supreme Court’s recent refusal to take up several states’ appeals of judicial decisions reversing voter bans, and the subsequent increased issuance of marriage licenses to homosexual couples — then marriage may have finally been divorced, so to speak, from motherhood. Because who becomes the mother in an ersatz marriage between two men?

(Proponents might say that it matters not, that motherhood and the belief that children benefit from the social cues and male-and-female examples they get in traditional marriages are antiquated notions. Odd that some people who have grown up in same-sex households tell a different story.)

How did we get to this point? Blogger Matt Walsh, on a new platform with an inaugural post entitled There is No Such Thing as Marriage Equality, wrote,

Sometime between the divorce rate skyrocketing and out-of-wedlock births reaching 40 percent nationwide, it became obvious that our society has very little energy for preserving, defending, respecting, or even participating in marriage.

Amid conflicting reports over whether the divorce rate is continuing to rise or has never really approached the 50% figure often reported, sometimes it seems that the only people actively pursuing marriage are homosexual couples. In recent years they have certainly pursued it with vigor, often decrying the unfairness of how well our society treated married couples and ultimately dismissing accommodations society made for their relationships, because those accommodations weren’t sweeping enough and did not cover tax and other property benefits. As James Taranto wrote two years ago,

Gays are interested in marriage for two reasons. The first is because it provides concrete benefits in areas such as health care and inheritance. The second — the reason why they have by and large rejected the compromise of “civil unions” and insist on the word marriage — is because it implies an affirmation that homosexual relationships are morally and socially equal to heterosexual ones.

Walsh, however, argues that the latter can never obtain, and enumerates two key differences that distinguish marriage from the marriage-like arrangements of homosexual couples. First, that “one involves people of the same sex, the other does not.” That difference seems clear enough, and to it Walsh adds that “in one there is never any possibility of procreation, whereas in the other there is.” (I might quibble enough to word that as, “in one there is never any possibility of direct procreation, whereas in the other there is at least the theoretical or implied possibility,” but those distinctions are quite minor.)

After pointing out those quite basic differences, Walsh considers whether they are really that significant:

This is a country where we go out and buy new iPhones because they’re slightly different from the iPhones we bought 14 months ago. We pay for upgraded seats on an airplane because they’re slightly better than the seats three rows back. We cry discrimination and persecution if we find out that our coworker makes slightly more than us, or has a slightly bigger office, or a slightly more comfortable chair. We purchase TVs for a slightly clearer picture. In other words, we find immense, world-shattering connotations in the faintest little cosmetic changes and deviations, yet we struggle to appreciate the difference between heterosexual and homosexual couples; a difference that, if I must remind you, involves the creation of human life.

A man and a woman can get together and make a person. They can, between the two of them, conceive a human child….

Of course, the birth control industry and Planned Parenthood would like for us to see our procreative capacity as some minor and unimpressive little nuisance, but that’s only because they’ve got a product to sell. In reality, we can say what we want about it, but we can’t say that it’s immaterial. A man and a woman can make a baby. This means something. A man and a man cannot. This also means something.

Whatever it means, it means at least that the two relationships differ from one another. They are not equal. One is something, the other is something else. They are not the same. They are not equal.

Some people may appreciate a metaphor for how differences in substance warrant differences in terminology. When tobacco is shredded and rolled into small papers for smoking, we refer to the result as “cigarettes,” but when marijuana is treated likewise we refer to the result as “joints.” (In fact, to call the latter a “marijuana cigarette” is often derided or ridiculed as a mark of cluelessness, even though it seems to be a technically accurate description.) The internal constituents are different, and that difference is significant enough that the latter was given a completely different name. By this metaphor, what we seem to need is a new term for the homosexual version of “marriage.”

It is possible to say that what the courts have done — and it has largely been a judicial effort, because few jurisdictions have voted affirmatively to sanction homosexual “marriage” — is to make homosexual and heterosexual relationships equal under the law, a distinction that, were it to be applied generally to the text of the Declaration of Independence, might lead to a quite different interpretation of that document. In my mind the question then becomes, does society derive enough benefit from that new treatment that it should feel compelled to regard homosexual relationships the same way it regards heterosexual relationships?

I invite anyone who answers “yes” to present their argument in the comments, refraining from canards like “fairness” and presenting clear benefits to society as a whole.

In anticipation of being enlightened, I will present here four separate arguments of why society should be under no such compulsion to accord homosexual relationships the same honor as traditional marriage:

  • An argument from history. Did any civilization, at any time before the modern era, sanction legal, permanent homosexual relationships? Commenters are welcome to present examples, but so far as I can ascertain, even in civilizations in which homosexual activity was tolerated (e.g., ancient Persia), “marriage” was still limited to men and women. I understand that even recently some cultures still subscribed, openly or not, to the “women are for children, men are for pleasure” idea, but even there “marriage” was of the traditional kind.
  • An argument from the “norm.” In statistics, the “average” or “mean” can also be called the “norm.” Alternately (or perhaps similarly), in sociology, psychology, and education, the “norm” is a usual, expected, or even “average” behavior. Even though homosexual behavior might be “regular” or “routine” for those who practice it, and perhaps even “natural” and “normal” for them in that sense, when we consider sexual preferences on a population basis we must acknowledge that homosexuality is a societal outlier, and unlikely ever to be a societal “norm.” The question then becomes whether societal constructs — especially ones we might consider societal “institutions” — should be built on societal norms. Perhaps a case could be made that such constructs and institutions should be built on other foundations, but the question still remains as to why society should expand the institution, the “norm,” of marriage to include homosexual relationships. (Even if that is a matter upon which reasonable people may disagree, it does not mean accommodation for homosexual unions should be denied; accommodations could even be expanded, and those relationships could be honored in their own way, without according those relationships the status of marriages.)
  • An argument from philosophy. Immanuel Kant formulated the idea of the categorical imperative, in which human behavior is held to a standard higher than that of simply achieving certain ends. The imperative holds that we should act in such a way that our actions would become the basis for universal law. Above, we pointed out that homosexuality is unlikely ever to achieve the status of a societal “norm,” and it is difficult to imagine even the most dedicated supporter of marriage between homosexuals suggesting that homosexual behavior should be a categorical imperative, i.e., that homosexuality should become a universal law. To state such a proposition would be tantamount, it seems, to extolling the death of the human race through attrition, because of
  • An argument from biology. It seems safe to say (as Walsh did, quoted above) that homosexual coupling cannot produce offspring. It seems equally safe to say that without either engaging in heterosexual sex or enlisting technical assistance, homosexuals cannot produce offspring. This is not to say that homosexuality is automatically anti-evolutionary, because it is possible that a low incidence of homosexuality in a population actually confers some overall evolutionary benefit by reducing the competition for reproducing mates. Even if that is the case, however, homosexual coupling remains a biologically null proposition.

If, then, marriage is still to be considered a societal construct in which children can be born and raised in relative security — i.e., an institution derived from and devoted to “motherhood” — then homosexual “marriage” seems to fail on the “born” criterion. However, if marriage and motherhood are henceforth to be considered separate and unequal, then the question becomes whether any benefits of recognizing same-sex marriages outweigh the risks. And there are risks.

In the wake of the 09/11/01 attack, many on one side of the political aisle asked a form of the question, “Why do they hate us?” and stopped at the easy answer of US military presence in the Persian Gulf region. Fewer are likely to acknowledge that other societies find US cultural exports and societal forays into increasing decadence to be inimical to social order, perhaps because that would require them to take credit for being partly responsible for those societies’ animosity toward us. Are proponents of homosexual “marriage” willing to accept the possibility that widespread acceptance of the practice and legitimizing of homosexual unions may increase, rather than decrease, the animosity that certain societies feel toward the US? This is not, in itself, a reason to withhold approval; however, it should be noted as a risk factor and accepted with open eyes.

A point of clarification. Those who disagree with the arguments above so much that they feel dismay, disgust, or disapprobation may not have made it this far at all; however, it may be important here to note what I am NOT saying. I am NOT saying that homosexuals should stop being homosexual. Be who you are, and be true to yourself. I am NOT saying that homosexuals should be persecuted, vilified, or attacked. No one should seek to do you harm based on your sexual preference or your adult, consensual, sexual practice. I am NOT saying that homosexuals should be prevented or discouraged from forming lifelong committed pair bonds and enjoying personal- and property-related benefits from those relationships. Love whom you will, and love them well.

Back to the topic of marriage, it may be said that the “purpose” of marriage — i.e., the reason marriage became a societal institution bridging time and culture — was to provide for stable family relationships and the orderly transmission of property within a family. If that is the case, then would there be any reason to deny those benefits to families formed by homosexual pairings? Family units based on marriage provided a way that people could understand where (or with whom) they “belonged,” and served as a generally-recognized mechanism by which property could be maintained, improved, and passed on, but other mechanisms such as adoption have also been available to achieve those ends. Recognition of family-based property rights within a community reduced the likelihood (and the fear) that non-family would swoop in after a member died and divide the member’s property, leaving the family out. There seems to be no reason to leave homosexual couples open to such predations. (In some respects, therefore, and perhaps worthy of a separate discussion, “family” may not have to be equated with “marriage.”)

But there is that small matter of the historical link between “marriage” and “motherhood.” If marriage was only a social convention to provide for identification and inheritance, then “motherhood” need not have been its basis. Yet it was.

In the end, our society will choose and in the process will either agree or fragment even more than we already have. Perhaps society has already chosen. As noted in Did The Supreme Court Just Legalize Gay Marriage?, “this legal climate change becomes a kind of fait accompli.”

The road ahead is unlikely to be smooth, however, if Walsh’s prediction comes true:

‘Gay marriage’ and abortion are the holiest liberal sacraments because they alter the nature of life and of the family. If progressives can … remodel the family in service of their political agenda, and if these little fine tunes become accepted and promoted in the mainstream, then their agenda can go anywhere and do anything.

Indeed, re-defining marriage once means that it may continue to be re-defined. It seems all manner of restrictions on marriage could go by the boards and open the marriage relationship to any sort of preferences, if enough people agree that the restrictions are antiquated or violate some supposed rights. If the word loses its meaning, people will be free to define it however they wish.

But, it must be said, words do change meaning. Language evolves, and so does society. We may even think of society itself as evolutionary. Social structures have certainly provided evolutionary benefits, in that they made it more likely for our tribes to survive when the world was young and we were “red in tooth and claw.” Social structures will likely continue to change, and it remains to be seen if various societal mutations will produce the kind of benefits that confer long-term survival advantages; in essence, whether societal evolution — societal “natural selection,” if you will — augurs in our favor.

Society now is under different pressures than society in antiquity. It would seem that our society faces fewer existential pressures than society did in the past, and in response has magnified the perceived pressures — and may, to a certain extent, even have invented imaginary pressures that are pushing it in new, untested directions. So what price are we willing to pay, individually and as a society, to maintain — or to eliminate — historical social institutions, such as “matrimony,” that we have in common?

___

P.S. Another point of clarification. In addition to the things noted above that I am NOT saying in this piece, note I am NOT presenting any arguments based on the Bible, because I do not believe those apply. Why? First, because Scripture is not US law or any local code. Second, because the behavioral injunctions in Scripture are made to particular people — first to the Jews via the Law and the Prophets, and second to Christian believers — and therefore do not constitute requirements for nonbelievers. I am not aware of anything in Scripture that requires a Biblical standard to be applied to nonbelievers; in contrast, it seems to me that only when a person becomes a believer and accepts Scripture as the guide for their life should they be held to the standards it espouses — and even then, with grace.

Facebooktwitterpinterestlinkedinmailby feather

May You Find What You Seek

Here’s wishing you and yours a fine and productive Explorers’ Day!*

Explorers Club building sign
(“Explorers Club building sign,” by Curious Expeditions, on Flickr under Creative Commons.)

In the spirit of all who sailed off into the unknown, may you find what you seek or, failing that, may you discover something even more wondrous and worthwhile.

___
*Or Discoverers’ Day, if you prefer. As I’ve pointed out elsewhere, if we have to celebrate all the Presidents together, we ought to kludge some of these other categories together as well.

Facebooktwitterpinterestlinkedinmailby feather

Are You Altruistic? Maybe It’s Your Amygdala

Did you do a good turn today? If you feel compelled sometimes to do something particularly altruistic, you may have a particularly well-developed amygdala.

A Good Deed Is Never Forgotten
(Painting, “A Good Deed Is Never Forgotten,” by Pierre Nicolas Legrand (1758-1829), in the Dallas Museum of Art. Image by Rodney, on Flickr under Creative Commons.)

Researchers at Georgetown University have been delving into the brains of people who are particularly altruistic — even studying people who have donated kidneys to complete strangers — as noted in The Biology Of Altruism: Good Deeds May Be Rooted In The Brain. Using functional MRI scans, principal investigator Abigail Marsh examined the structures of their brains and their brain activity while they took tests and looked at specific images. For example, they showed subjects “pictures of different facial expressions, including happiness, fear, anger, sadness and surprise.”

Most of the tests didn’t find any differences between the brains of the altruistic donors and the people who had not been donors. Except, Marsh says, for a significant difference in a part of the brain called the amygdala, an almond-shaped cluster of nerves that is important in processing emotion.

… The amygdala was significantly larger in the altruists …. Additionally, the amygdala in the altruists was extremely sensitive to the pictures of people displaying fear or distress.

The more we learn about the brain, the more remarkable it is! This finding makes sense to me, since altruism depends, at least in part, on the ability to imagine oneself in another person’s dire circumstances, and then to act to change those circumstances.

I found this part particularly interesting:

These findings are the polar opposite to research Marsh conducted on a group of psychopaths. Using the same tests as with the altruists, Marsh found that psychopaths have significantly smaller, less active amygdalas. More evidence that the amygdala may be the brain’s emotional compass, super-sensitive in altruists and blunted in psychopaths, who seem unresponsive to someone else’s distress or fear.

So if altruism is your default state, it may be because you have a very active amygdala — a highly tuned “emotional compass.” And for those of us who are not very altruistic, it may be that we have some traits in common with … psychopaths. That’s not the most comforting thought, but perhaps this will help: Aristotle taught that we become virtuous by developing and practicing the habit of being virtuous, and we have the Golden Rule (e.g., Matthew 7:12) as one guideline we can use as we do so.

So, do a good turn today!

Facebooktwitterpinterestlinkedinmailby feather

Disney Magic Not Working So Well in Europe

From The Guardian, a report that Disneyland Paris — once called “Euro Disney” — is in financial trouble.

le château de Disneyland Paris
(“le château de Disneyland Paris,” by Louis Engival, on Flickr under Creative Commons.)

From the article, Disneyland Paris forced to ask for €1bn emergency rescue,

The theme park, which was dubbed a “cultural Chernobyl” when it opened 22 years ago, is haemorrhaging visitors. It drew in 14.1 million over the past 12 months, a drop of 800,000 on the previous year and 1.5 million lower than 2012…. But experts believe that to start making money it needs to draw in at least 15 million people a year. The park last turned a profit in 2008 and expects to lose €110m to €120m this year.

So, as a result, the Walt Disney company, which owns 40% of the Paris attraction, is stepping in for “its third multimillion-euro bailout of its French offspring,” to the tune of a billion euros (at today’s exchange rate, $1.27B, some in cash and some converting debt into shares) and ten years of “breathing space” on the remainder of its €1.75B ($2.21B) debt.

It surprised me to learn that, “While visitor numbers are down, the park still pulls in more people than the Louvre and the Eiffel Tower combined, making it Europe’s biggest tourist attraction.” I never even considered going to Disneyland Paris when Jill and I were in Europe for the World Science Fiction Convention this past August — not that our entry fee would have made a dent in that amount of debt!

I’m not sure that there’s any big lesson in all this — you can take it as a cautionary tale; as an example that just because something works in one place it’s not guaranteed to work somewhere else; or as encouragement that even highly successful companies don’t always succeed when they pursue new ventures — but it was interesting to me.

Facebooktwitterpinterestlinkedinmailby feather

Teenage Wasteland: Media Inaccuracy, or Something Else?

When is a 19-year-old not an adult? When it serves someone else’s purpose to label him a “teenager.”

Adults Only
(“Adults Only,” by Pam Morris, on Flickr under Creative Commons.)

According to CNN,

Before authorities arrested him at O’Hare International Airport and accused him of attempting to provide aid to ISIS, a teen from the Chicago suburbs left behind a letter for his parents.

Mohammed Hamzah Khan, 19, wrote that he was leaving the United States and on the way to join ISIS, according to a criminal complaint. He invited his family to join him in the three-page letter, which authorities found in the bedroom he shared with a sibling in Bolingbrook, Illinois. But he warned them not to tell anyone about his travel plans, the complaint said.

The headline — which seems disingenuous in the extreme, given the opening paragraphs — is, “Was arrested teen on his way to join ISIS?”

Throughout the CNN article, as well as on NBC and ABC and other outlets, the young man is referred to as a “teen.” Correct in the strict sense of the word, perhaps, but misleading: this was an adult, of legal age, despite being technically a teenager.

Someone casually reading the headline could make the honest mistake that this was a minor, rather than an adult responsible for his actions. To persist in calling him a “teen” is to imply that his choice to pursue affiliation with ISIS was some youthful folly, rather than a deliberate decision.

The correct news headline — the accurate news headline — would have been “Chicago Man Arrested on His Way to Join ISIS.”

I leave it to the reader to consider why journalists and editors might have made this choice.

Facebooktwitterpinterestlinkedinmailby feather

Does the Human Eye Prove that God Exists?

To answer the question right out of the gate, I’d say no, because no single phenomenon or example can “prove” that God exists.


(Someone is watching you ….)

The question comes from the headline of an article in The Telegraph — in the “film” section, no less — that discusses what a wondrous mechanism the human eye is, with its “astonishing inbuilt systems.”

Take, for example, a little trick called the vestibulo-ocular reflex (VOR). In short, it’s our own personal Steadicam — an inbuilt muscular response that stabilises everything we see, by making tiny imperceptible eye movements in the opposite direction to where our head is moving. Without VOR, any attempts at walking, running — even the minuscule head tremors you make while you read these words — would make our vision blurred, scattered and impossible to comprehend.

As one who finds very jittery camera work in movies (like District 9) and some video game action (like the rolling ball in Katamari Damacy) very disorienting — to the point of physical illness — I am very grateful for the VOR!

But that’s not all:

… researchers have discovered the retina is doing a huge amount of pre-processing itself – and that as light passes through the retina’s several dense layers of neurons, a lot of detail like colour, motion, orientation and brightness are determined.

When I took a laser safety course (many years ago), we were told that the retina was put together opposite the way an optical engineer would have designed it, because the rods and cones actually point backward, into the retina itself, instead of forward toward the lens. This newly-found pre-processing function may have something to do with that, though personally I wonder if turning the sensors around would make our eyes more susceptible to damage from very intense lights.

Things like that make the question of deliberate design vs. development by natural selection interesting. As the article puts it,

Even today, Christians and creationists believe that Charles Darwin himself was troubled by its existence — seizing upon an (oft-misquoted) aside in Origin of Species, where Darwin remarked that the whole idea of something so flawless “could have been formed by natural selection, seems, I freely confess, absurd in the highest degree.”

The full Darwin quote, with the important next sentence, is:

To suppose that the eye with all its inimitable contrivances for adjusting the focus to different distances, for admitting different amounts of light, and for the correction of spherical and chromatic aberration, could have been formed by natural selection, seems, I freely confess, absurd in the highest degree. Yet reason tells me, that if numerous gradations from a perfect and complex eye to one very imperfect and simple, each grade being useful to its possessor, can be shown to exist; if further, the eye does vary ever so slightly, and the variations be inherited, which is certainly the case; and if any variation or modification in the organ be ever useful to an animal under changing conditions of life, then the difficulty of believing that a perfect and complex eye could be formed by natural selection, though insuperable by our imagination, can hardly be considered real.

Thus something that seems absurd may still be possible, and even reasonable. The question is whether it matters. For instance, whether it matters to a believer that sufficiently different eyes can be understood by natural selection to lead to the human eye. Or whether it matters to an unbeliever that the believer attributes the eye’s complexity to the influence of a creative God.

The eye still exists, and some of us can praise God for it even though its existence is insufficient to prove that God exists.

And that’s okay. After all, faith is “the evidence of things not seen.”*

___
*Hebrews 11:1 (KJV)

Facebooktwitterpinterestlinkedinmailby feather